brimstoneSalad wrote:In the island scenario, I was imagining a limited sustainable source of food (as in reality). Like the plants on the island can only support one person, but do so indefinitely. If two people eat their fill, they will both die because the plants will be wiped out.
Ah, got it. I guess one would have to be vegan and the other a breatharian.
brimstoneSalad wrote:Exactly, which is why fairness under the LAW is important, because of the consequences. But fairness itself isn't always inherently good. And practical unfairness that is fair in the context of the social contract (like us being able to hire who we want, and basically make the choice to be assholes in the greater "fair" context of free speech and freedom of choice) may be worth it in terms of the other freedoms that affords. It's always a trade off, and we have to look at what we gain or lose. Fairness, whatever that arbitrarily means, does not define the best case outcome.
True.
Usually you define fairness as getting merit-based returns. Not equality, but equal opportunity and all that stuff.
brimstoneSalad wrote:Sometimes it does, sometimes it doesn't. But if you try to force it at the cost of other freedoms, it's usually worse. Remember that fairness is not a single goal, and can be subjective. To a millionaire, it does not seem fair to take his money, which belongs to him, when he didn't do anything 'wrong' in terms of violating the social contract.
He didn’t, but it's fair to try to correct the effects of the coin flip that happened a long time ago. Millionaires most often have not gotten there just by virtue of their own merit, they've always been rich (there are exceptions here of course). A more substantive inheritance tax should take care of that.
I think that, statistically, the rule is generally reversed for the super rich, like multi-billionaires - they're more likely to have worked their way to the top. The abnormally substantive result of their work should be due to some flaw in the contract, or in the lacking ability to prevent deviations from the contract, and that can be adjusted for if you can find the common cause. I guess it's pretty easy to find it, it's just more difficult to gather enough support to fix it.
I’m referring strictly to what’s fair here, not about how that affects the outcome. Based on the contract, it’s not fair to take away the millionaire's property. But it is fair to adjust for the unfairness within the contract if the practical results clearly indicate that it exists.
brimstoneSalad wrote:Yes, but fairness is a poor rule in many cases, because it's so subjective. Fair to whom? We need to abide by the social contract -- or at least abide by its punishments -- but that in itself can be exploited to create differences in well being. The rich get richer, and the poor get poorer, because the rich are protected from the overwhelming poor too; they got their money "fair" and square, playing the game.
Then the game is rigged. Fix the contract. Or don’t, if the current contract results in better overall outcomes. But usually it won’t. It’s a matter of testing if that’s the case.
brimstoneSalad wrote:Redistribution of wealth in the early days of communism provides a good example. Sometimes the new system you're trying to build is just inherently unstable, and in trying to fix things based on some ideological notion of improvement you just make them worse until, over time, they return to the original status quo.
Does that mean it's impossible to do right, just because nobody has done it? No. But it means we should be cautious in trying to fix something when there's no evidence of the new system being able to work in practice.
I agree 100%.
That’s why I support incremental change based on needs brought to light by empirical analysis, rather than bulldozing down a current system to make way for a shiny new one. The new type of system can't be stable because it’s top-down. You can’t force people to internalize its ideas, especially when they’re logically inconsistent due to ideology.
Communism is a good example here, but then there are versions and versions of communism.
brimstoneSalad wrote:I think you're mistakenly considering events and consequences to be fundamentally different. Consequentialism is a sum of events (such as an instance of well being, or a moment of happiness, or an action of altruism). If there is only one event (one action, one moment, etc.), there is still a sum to be evaluated. The action itself is still part of the sum of the consequences.
Deontology fails to consider the sum of the following events caused by the original, and only considers the first event itself.
Virtue ethics are typically a form of consequentialism.
Hmm... It might actually be true that I'm not getting something, I still do have difficulty making a clear distinction between utilitarianism and consequentialism as a whole (as it's portrayed in the sources I've come in contact with until now). I now understand your definition a bit better and it sounds alright to me, but I'll have to do some more reading on that and I'll get back to you if anything's still unclear.
brimstoneSalad wrote:You misunderstand again. Consequentialism does not equal utilitarianism. A single event can easily be moral or immoral in consequentialsim. Consider altruistic consequentialism, not utilitarianism. Which examples demonstrate more altruistic value?
My initial reaction was: Who cares, when you only look at the consequences in that event? But as I said, I might have an off picture of consequentionalism and just confuse it with utilitarianism.
It's clear which demonstrate more altruistic value. So the right kind of consequence is the one maximizing well-being achieved through altruistic means in your view?
About altruism and egoism - In a society where each person values himself only as a means for each other person, who in turn value themselves as means for each other person, then everyone receives the benefits of an exclusively altruistic society, so everyone is well-off. On the other hand, if each person lives exclusively for their own interests, everyone receives the benefit that they are able to create for themselves. Sure, there are conflicts of interests, but that affects interactions between egoists just as much as the decisions made by altruists when considering who to care about more.
First I thought that the results of the two systems should be the same, but people have different levels of ability, so I guess the first one should generate more egalitarian results than the latter. But then the sum total of the benefits should be the same.
brimstoneSalad wrote:Virtue ethics is usually consequential. You do something because the consequences are it increases your virtue. And virtues are virtuous because the consequences of having those virtues is on the whole good. It's sort of a second order formulation -- a simplification for practice -- but quite valid.
Virtue ethics is a good study of the extent of consequentialism.
Traditional normative moral theories fall into three types -
Teleological theories seek to identify some supreme end or best way of life, and reduce the right and the virtuous to the promotion of this good.
Deontological theories seek to identify a supreme principle or laws of morality independent of the good, and subordinate the pursuit of the good to conformity with the moral law, independent of consequences.
Virtue theories take phenomena of approval and disapproval to be fundamental, and derive the right and the good from them. They are based on the spontaneous tendencies of observers to approve and disapprove of people's conduct, not just on taking actions that lead to the most moral ends.
For example (virtue): You can still be a pretty shitty person even if the totality of the consequences of your actions isn't less moral than a nice person's.
I'll donate 1 milion$ to a charity for animals and continue being a carnist. I'm doing way more good for the animals than my vegan neighbour who struggles to put food on the table for their family. But that's only when you look at things in absolute terms. Relative to my means, I'm doing less, so I'm the less virtuous person.
or
A person is a carnist because they've never come in contact with veganism and they don't possess the mental faculties to come up with the logic of veganism on their own. There are immoral consequences of their actions, but they’re not really an immoral person because of that.
Another person is a carnist although they understand and even agree with the vegan logic but "bacon tho". Same consequences, very different levels of virtue.
What you do with what you have says a lot about how moral you are. And the intention behind what you do also says something about your virtue, even though the result might go to shit due to miscalculation. That’s more information than just considering the morality of the ends of one’s actions. If you take actions specifically with the intention of creating moral consequences, then I guess you'd be virtuous within the framework of consequentialism too. But what about if your actions accidentally result in moral consequences?
brimstoneSalad wrote:I see why you think that, but it's not a good fit for the definition of morality. This is a semantic issue, and one of the innate philosophical principle of valuing the interests of others. Egoism is amorality (interest for the self is the default), Altruism is morality, Utilitarianism is an odd mix of the two. Sadism is immorality -- as the opposite of altruism (should utilitarianism include negative interests for others too?). When you look at the full spectrum, it becomes more clear why altruism is morality, and how it stands in relation to other primitive or elemental considerations of interest.
Yeah, I understand.
brimstoneSalad wrote:Aggregating is more of a practical matter. Ideally you consider individuals, but we just can't do that. We need rules of thumb to put things into practice. This is similar to the logic behind virtue ethics. People are bad at calculating moral outcome for each situation on the fly: too many variables, and it can end in analysis paralysis. Sometimes a less precise method actually works better, and turns out more accurate on average because it's better put into practice.
Right.
brimstoneSalad wrote:I agree. If I see evidence of something working, I'm for it. Socialism is working pretty well in Europe; it's probably worth moving in that direction more in North America. But that's all about the social contract -- the rule of law -- within which fairness is of paramount importance, but also in part defined.
Once we are legally equal, is it really more fair, or does it promote good consequences, to force more "equality" upon people in their personal lives to compensate for personal choices and systemic social prejudices?
I am not convinced it does promote good consequences -- if there are ten poor people jobs and ten rich people jobs, and they all need to be done, I don't think it matters who is in which jobs, or if the genders or skin colors are disproportionately represented in the two, as long as this isn't a product of the LAW forcing this, since they're all humans.
You're not wrong, BUT I think there's more to it:
Any clear disproportion in sex, race or any other arbitrary criteria like that within those jobs means that there is something causing it, since differences between those groups of people are not
that large. It might not be a systemic legal cause, but it is something. If there wasn't any discrimination, be it conscious or involuntary*, we would see a different distribution.
This sort of discrimination might not matter to the overall economy ( I don't know, that should be verified empirically), but it does matter to people. Do we want the world to only be efficient or do we want it to also be nice and warm and fuzzy? By that I mean:
If a group of individuals feels underrepresented in a "good" (desirable) category of jobs or whatever, they'll be less satisfied. Individuals do identify with certain groups - even those based on arbitrary criteria like gender, race, sexual orientation -, it's human nature. And they also more readily extend their empathy to the members of the group which they themselves feel they belong to (maybe you don't - kudos to you and education and reason). That might be irrational, but we shouldn't be concerned with how people
should think, but with how they
do think. It makes sense to talk about different categories of people because that's how emotions work in most humans.
When one category is randomly disadvantaged, all individuals within that category are hurt to some extent, simply because they identify with the category. Until people's mentalities are evolved enough to stop differentiating between humans like that, this sort of fairness will matter to them and will affect their well-being. So maybe it's pragmatic to take fairness based on random criteria seriously for now, since it clearly does create consequences for people.
It's easier to get people to understand that various categories might
be different but should not be
treated differently, rather than make them understand that those differences are irrelevant in the first place. Similar result, more cost-effective.
That's how you get the 'let's encourage diversity' policies. I agree, diversity shouldn't mean much in itself, because it would only be a side-effect if we stopped caring about those differences in the first place.
It's like what you said about genders in another thread: Until we evolve to stop seing gender and sexuality as relevant criteria, it does make sense to promote the lgbt cause.
*For example it can be involuntary just by the effects of socially constructed gender roles, where females simply show a preference for certain areas because they've been conditioned that way. Does this actually hurt them that much, since they're the ones chosing their job anyway?
They do have some freedom to make their choice, but not full freedom. Social conditioning does slightly restrict their freedom to make a choice out of the full range of options by highlighting some options and making others less visible. It's like what Google does when you search for anything.
You still get to decide which links to click, but some links get shoved in your face more than others. Is that a fair comparison?
(While you can argue that Google does this using a pattern that's more likely to help you make a good choice, since the full range of options would overwhelm you. I don't think you can say the same about gender roles.)
Does that ultimately hurt women? Yes, if they end up getting payed less.
Then again, should we care that females and not other human beings are getting payed less? Yes, if they identify as female and they feel disadvantaged economically as a result of their identity. If you feel like you're getting disadvantaged economically as a result of your own (lack of) merit or ability rather than your identity, then you might feel better about it. Fairness works both ways. Attitudes are important.
brimstoneSalad wrote:And I'm definitely not convinced that the effort in changing social attitudes on these topics pays good dividends, or is an important part in vegan outreach (i.e. intersectionality).
Yeah I've also been following the intersectionality discussion (before it got sidetracked). Social attitudes are important, though I'm not sure if we should mix up veganism with other stuff. I'm still forming my opinion on this issue.
For now, I don't really see how it could hurt to reach out to potential vegans and acknowledge their different needs and difficulties though. It might just not be very cost-effective.